HR in particular
https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=AhRBsJYWR8Q
Human rights today have the kind of status that the divine right of kings had in the Middle Ages.
0:05
They are so deeply ingrained in our political thinking,
0:09
that imagining a society without them seems almost impossible.
0:14
We all know the famous line from the Declaration of Independence:
0:17
"We hold these truths to be self-evident, that all men are created equal,
0:22
that they are endowed by their creator with certain unalienable rights,"
0:27
But we should beware of what seems self-evident.
0:29
In many cases, what seems self-evident is less an indication of what is correct or indubitable,
0:36
and more an indication of our biases, an effect of the time and place we live in.
0:41
One of the most influential liberal political philosophers of the 20th century, John Rawls, once even stated that:
0:48
"Human rights are not the consequence of a particular philosophy,
0:52
nor of one way among others of looking at the world.
0:55
They are not tied to the cultural tradition of the West alone,
0:59
even if it was within this tradition that they were formulated for the first time.
1:03
They just follow from the definition of justice."
1:07
That human rights "simply follow from the definition of justice" is, at the very least, a strange claim,
1:13
because the notion of "justice" has been theorized at least since the ancient Greeks.
1:18
Whereas the doctrine of human rights was not fully formulated until the 17th century.
1:23
Can we really untie the definition of justice from the vast majority of the terms' history?
1:28
Whenever we feel like some notion or idea is impossible to do without, there is a kind of therapy we can utilize.
1:36
It's called history.
1:38
By seeing how the idea of human rights emerged,
1:41
we can then situate it as a product of a particular time and place.
1:45
And those hopefully remove the limits that it places on our political imagination.
1:50
A crucial distinction is in order before we begin:
1:53
the distinction between objective rights and subjective rights.
1:57
Objective rights state what is right in general.
2:00
For example, "It is right to bury the dead," "It is right to obey your parents,"
2:05
or "It is right to serve your community."
2:08
Notice that these do not attribute rights to an individual.
2:12
They do not state whose right it is to bury the dead.
2:15
Merely that it is right.
2:17
Subjective rights, on the other hand, are rights that are attributed to an individual, a subject.
2:23
Hence, subjective.
2:25
Examples would include the familiar rights from the Declaration of Independence.
2:29
"I have the right to liberty,"
2:31
"I have the right to property," "I have the right to a fair trial."
2:35
These do not state what is right generally,
2:38
but rather speak of rights as something that someone possesses.
2:42
And it is this category, subjective rights, that constitutes the idea of human rights that we are all so familiar with.
2:49
Something that each human being owns, merely by virtue of being human.
2:54
Today, we pretty much identify "rights" as such with subjective rights.
2:58
If someone speaks of rights, more often than not we can assume they're speaking about the subjective variety.
3:04
Yet, they're actually an incredibly recent invention.
3:08
When, for example, ancient Greeks spoke of what is right, or lawful, or just,
3:13
they have the objective conception in mind.
3:15
To them the idea of subjective right would probably be incomprehensible.
3:21
In fact, sentences in the form of "I have the right to..." something,
3:26
are not even possible to construct in ancient Greek.
3:29
Ancient Greek philosophers commonly saw what is right, what is lawful,
3:34
as being determined by the moral order of the world itself.
3:38
What is right was not to be found in individuals, but in the harmonious order of things.
3:44
In the relationships between the different parts of the world and ones community.
3:48
Roman law famously defined justice as: "giving each person what is due to him"
3:53
Reading this through the spectacles of our times,
3:56
we might assume that what "giving each person what is due to him" means, is something like
4:01
"respecting each person's individual property rights."
4:04
But, as I already mentioned, the notion of a subjective right had not even been formulated at the time.
4:10
What was due to a person was determined not by the individual rights they possessed,
4:15
but by their position in the larger community, and their relationship to the other members of the community.
4:21
The point of such distributive justice was to aim at social harmony,
4:25
something that can only be understood in light of the community as a whole,
4:29
rather than in terms of isolated individual rights.
4:33
So what changed this brand of justice, so different from the one common in our times?
4:38
What made it possible to think of rights as "subjective"?
4:42
Like many things in the history of ""the West,"" one thing in particular is crucial.
4:48
Christianity.
4:49
First of all, Christianity conceived of each individual as having a soul.
4:54
Something which places each person in direct relationship to God,
4:57
and thus gives each person a kind of absolute value.
5:01
Because the soul exists independently both from one's personal qualities and the community one belongs to,
5:08
it becomes possible to view individuals not as the specific members of their community,
5:13
but instead as abstract human beings, each being equal in sharing a common essence.
5:20
Because the soul is both universal and eternal,
5:23
human beings could now be viewed in abstraction from both time and space.
5:27
Independently from the position they occupy in their community, or the world more generally.
5:33
Secondly: certain Christians, for example: William of Ockham,
5:36
eventually argued that if the moral law is inherent in the order of things, it leaves no freedom for God.
5:43
As God must follow the order of things as well.
5:47
Because of this, gradually, the moral law came to be seen not as something inherent in the order of things,
5:53
but something stemming from the will of God.
5:55
The importance of "order" is replaced by the importance of "will".
6:00
Finally, because we are created by God, in the image of God,
6:03
it takes a small step to identify the will of God with the will of each individual.
6:09
Thus, the result is a morality built on universal abstract rights,
6:13
which emanate from the will of each individual, by virtue of a shared human essence.
6:18
We arrive at the full-fledged enlightenment conception of human rights.
6:23
Some might be surprised by the significant role played by Christianity in the development of human rights.
6:28
But this was made very clear in the writings of the theorists developing human rights themselves.
6:34
John Locke, for example, one of the main philosophical influences on the Declaration of Independence,
6:40
started his Theory of Rights from the claim that God owns us as property,
6:45
and therefore endows us with unalienable rights.
6:48
And this is stated in the Declaration of Independence itself:
6:51
"Humans are endowed by their creator with certain unalienable rights."
6:55
The religious parallels don't end there.
6:58
Human rights and belief in God are also similar in that both are supposed to be something self-evident,
7:04
rather than something you can discover empirically.
7:07
And just as nowadays, people claim that without the doctrine of human rights,
7:11
society would plunge into chaos.
7:13
So people used to argue that society would plunge into chaos without the belief in God.
7:18
So far I've mostly been talking about ideas. Namely, Christian ideas.
7:24
But ideas don't just float around in the heavens.
7:27
In order to be effective, they need to be established materially, in political and social life.
7:33
The influence of Christianity is clear.
7:35
But why is it that the ideology of human rights became so widely and rapidly accepted?
7:41
Specifically in the 17th century and onwards, when Christianity had existed much longer than that.
7:47
Well, if the ideas behind human rights are inseparable from Christian thought,
7:51
then their political influence is inseparable from the rise of capitalism.
7:56
In order for capitalism to kick off,
7:59
the emerging capitalists had to buy a plan that was previously owned communally,
8:04
for the subsistence of the people living on it, and turn it into land owned individually for profit.
8:10
This was known as the enclosure movement,
8:13
during which many peasants, who had previously worked on commonly owned land,
8:17
producing for their own consumption,
8:20
were forcibly and often violently removed from said land.
8:24
And, now property-less, were forced to work for a wage.
8:27
Thus people who previously saw themselves as part of a larger community,
8:31
working together to accomplish shared goals,
8:35
now became isolated and atomized individuals.
8:38
And the production process no longer responsible to their community,
8:42
but to their boss, the individual capitalist.
8:45
Collective solidarity was gradually replaced with individual competition.
8:50
Workers ceased being fellow members in a shared community,
8:53
and became individuals competing for a wage.
8:55
They became, in other words, individuals who got together in production
8:59
in the pursuit of their own private individual interests.
9:03
Workers pursuing a wage, and capitalists pursuing more capital.
9:08
The ideology of human rights went hand-in-hand with the situation.
9:12
It conceived of freedom primarily as negative freedom: freedom "from".
9:17
For example, freedom from interference.
9:20
Replacing the positive collective freedom people experienced in pursuit of shared goals before.
9:25
Competition led people to view each other as something that they must be protected from,
9:30
as something that constantly threatens to infringe on their ""rights.""
9:35
And this is also why social contract theory became so popular.
9:39
Positing that society was created through the establishment of a contract.
9:44
If people are seen as individualized and atomized by default,
9:48
and get together only in pursuit of their own self-interest,
9:51
then the only conceivable way to form a society is to sign a contract.
9:57
This led to the strict separation between what Hegel called civil society on the one hand and the political state on the other.
10:04
Civil society is the society of the market,
10:08
of private individuals pursuing their private interests independently of anyone else.
10:13
The political state, in contrast, is the sphere in which people get together to make common decisions.
10:18
Fixing the excesses of the civil sphere.
10:21
Liberal society was shaped by this fundamental split.
10:25
Private individuals on one side, and the state with its offices, courts, army, and police force on the other.
10:32
Hence, Marx writes:
10:33
"Above all we note the fact that the so called rights of man
10:39
are nothing but the rights of a member of civil society
10:42
i.e. the rights of egoistic man, of man separated from other men and from the community."
10:51
The separation between civil society and the political state splits the individual into two:
10:58
the private, egoistic individual of civil society on the one hand,
11:02
and the political man, the citizen of the political state, on the other.
11:06
This also creates a tension in the ideology of human rights,
11:10
because they're supposed to exist independently of any particular political system,
11:15
but can only be granted to a person if the state recognizes them as a citizen.
11:20
The abstract universal human being is in constant tension
11:24
with the particular citizen of a specific political community.
11:28
The way in which human rights view individuals as universal and abstract
11:32
was also befitting the capitalist production process.
11:36
Because when a capitalist hires workers
11:38
he views them as abstract individuals, defined only by their labor power.
11:43
And because the ideology of human rights posits that rights are formally equal for everyone,
11:48
it helps obscure the vast and real power imbalances that exists between real people.
11:53
For example, the state proclaims that the courts are fair,
11:57
because everyone has an equal right to a fair trial.
12:00
But this equal right obscures the fact that how "fair" your trial is, depends on the lawyer you can afford.
12:08
The doctrine of equal human rights does not actually make people equal.
12:12
It just allows them to be viewed in abstraction,
12:14
from everything that actually makes them the person that they are.
12:18
This is yet another tension found in human rights.
12:21
On the one hand, their supposed purpose is to protect the autonomy of the individual,
12:26
yet by its very nature, it must view human beings in abstraction
12:30
from everything that actually makes them an individual.
12:34
But, even given all of this, it could still be the case that human rights have a net positive value, right?
12:40
We should be careful not to commit a genetic fallacy here.
12:43
Judging that something is bad, solely based on where it came from or how it emerged.
12:49
It could be that rights are valuable,
12:50
even if they were originally declared to legitimate the interests of the emerging capitalist class.
12:56
However, I think that the problem with human rights
12:59
at least as we understand and implement them, is inherent to them.
13:04
To explain why we must ask what their fundamental problem is.
13:08
Let's begin from a starting point that is often overlooked or ignored in theory.
13:13
The enforcement of rights.
13:16
Liberal political theorists, when speaking of rights or laws,
13:20
often avoid speaking of their enforcement like the devil.
13:23
This is because the issue of enforcement brings to light the power dynamics at play.
13:29
Who has the power to enforce?
13:31
But in order for human rights to be effective, they have to be enforced.
13:36
Violently if necessary.
13:37
So who enforces them?
13:40
Well, those who have the power to enforce them.
13:43
Those who control the courts, the military, and the police force.
13:46
Namely the state. A state with the monopoly on violence.
13:51
And in order to enforce such rights they must be more powerful than you,
13:54
and have the permission to commit acts that you yourself cannot.
13:58
And who does the state serve?
14:00
Well, even if liberal ideology says that it serves society as a whole,
14:05
it must by its very nature serve those who fund it.
14:08
Otherwise, it would not receive the capital that allows it to exist in the first place.
14:13
And who primarily funds it?
14:16
The wealthy. In other words, the ruling class.
14:19
It is their interests that it must represent.
14:21
It's not a coincidence that some of the most influential human rights declarations were signed in palaces.
14:29
A fundamental tension immediately begins to emerge here.
14:32
In order for human rights to exist politically,
14:35
there must be someone vastly more powerful than you, giving you those rights in the first place.
14:41
Human rights, which are supposed to make everyone equal,
14:44
paradoxically depend on a fundamental power imbalance between groups with competing interests.
14:50
And if someone more powerful than you is giving you your rights, then they can also take them away.
14:56
But if this is the case, why would the state grant those rights at all?
15:00
Here Nietzsche's conception of rights in the Genealogy of Morals is very helpful.
15:05
He writes: "My rights - are the part of my power
15:09
which others have not merely conceded me, but which they wish me to preserve."
15:14
"How do these others arrive at that? First: through their prudence and fear and caution
15:20
whether in that they expect something similar from us in return,
15:24
or in that they consider that a struggle with us would be perilous or to no purpose."
15:29
So, say the working class is financially and politically impoverished.
15:33
Tired of the situation, they organize together in a militant labor movement and threaten to overthrow the state.
15:40
The state then recognizes the working class as powerful. Powerful enough to pose a threat.
15:46
And because they recognize this power, they decide to implement certain labor rights.
15:50
These rights are not implemented because the state is benevolent,
15:54
or because it's enacting some eternal moral law.
15:58
Rather, they are implementing these rights as a compromise between two competing powerful groups,
16:03
in the hope that this will appease the other party.
16:06
"That is how rights originate: recognized and guaranteed degrees of power."
16:11
This way of looking at rights is more embedded in social and material reality.
16:16
It helps us see how they emerge not as impartial eternal laws, but as the historical outcomes of struggle.
16:24
Nietzsche continues: "If power relationships undergo any material alteration,
16:29
rights disappear and new ones are created -
16:31
as is demonstrated in the continual disappearance and reformation of rights between nations."
16:38
"If our power is materially diminished,
16:41
the feeling of those who have hitherto guaranteed our rights changes:
16:47
they consider whether they can restore us to the full possession we formerly enjoyed -
16:52
if they feel unable to do so, they henceforth deny our "rights""
16:57
So to continue my example: if the working class ends up growing weaker,
17:02
the state that previously granted it additional rights, no longer sees them as necessary and take them away.
17:09
Kind of like what happened in the emergence of neoliberalism in the 80s with Reagan and Thatcher.
17:14
The elimination of previously won labor rights
17:17
corresponded to a rapid weakening of the labour movement.
17:21
In other words: the very existence of human rights
17:24
presupposes the existence of a power struggle of competing groups,
17:29
with the more powerful one granting rights to the weaker one.
17:33
As the journal Gegenstandpunkt writes: "Man has the right to be the servant of a master that attends to him:
17:39
that is the miserable substance of the great Enlightenment notion of the natural human right."
17:46
It's no wonder that the first two countries to declare human rights:
17:50
The United States and France, were also some of the last countries to abolish slavery.
17:55
This power dynamic that we see between classes also exists between countries.
18:01
Take the so-called "right of humanitarian intervention".
18:05
Something with no historical precedent, which states that one nation can invade another,
18:10
for the purpose of stopping human rights violations.
18:13
Who enforces the right of humanitarian intervention?
18:16
Well, again, those who have the power to do so. The militarily and economically powerful.
18:22
This creates a situation in which the powerful can use humanitarian intervention as a pretext
18:28
to invade, destabilize, and exploit other countries, like what the U.S. did with Yugoslavia, Libya, Syria, etc.
18:36
While themselves not being accountable to anyone for their own human rights violations.
18:41
Let me be clear here:
18:43
I'm not saying that all these problems will be fixed if we simply stop adhering to the doctrine of human rights.
18:50
Human rights are an outcome. A symptom of a specific social and political configuration,
18:56
and you don't fight the symptom, you fight the disease.
18:59
If we recognize the problem with human rights,
19:02
it is the social and political configuration that produces them that we have to change.
19:07
So long as we live under capitalism and the liberal political paradigm,
19:11
rights are absolutely necessary.
19:14
But if we limit our struggles to begging for the state to grant us rights,
19:18
we will never address the more fundamental problem that human rights are a response to.
19:23
The fundamental social and political imbalances that constitutes our society.
19:29
The split between civil society and the political states,
19:33
which is inseparable from the split between economic classes.
19:37
We can begin to see at this point that human rights and the divine right of kings
19:42
are actually very similar in significant respects.
19:45
Both are utilized by a minority of the population, the ruling class,
19:50
to justify its rule by appealing to something independent of society.
19:55
Some metaphysical or moral law.
19:57
Compare: "Sure, there are vast power imbalances between us,
20:01
but we're all subjects of God, and we, the kings, are merely carrying out his will."
20:08
And: "Sure, there are vast power imbalances between us,
20:12
but we're all bearers of rights, and we, the state, are merely enforcing those rights."
20:17
In other words: the ideology of human rights, like the ideology of the divine right of kings,
20:23
tries to naturalize a historically contingent political situation.
20:27
Portraying it as something necessary.
20:30
It involves an essential contradiction.
20:32
It declares human rights to be something that exists independently of states,
20:36
even though such human rights inherently presuppose the existence of a state.
20:40
So, what would need to be done in order to establish a society
20:45
that no longer produces or depends on the ideology of human rights?
20:50
It would have to be a society in which the significance of community has been restored.
20:55
A society where collective decision-making is not confined to the state,
20:59
but characterizes society as a whole, starting from the local level.
21:04
A society where production is not the affair of private individuals pursuing their self-interest,
21:09
but a socially planned process.
21:12
It is only when people reclaim power over their own lives and their own activities,
21:17
that they no longer need a state to grant them rights.
21:20
Because their powers would no longer be alienated by a state in the first place.
21:25
When decision-making is no longer the task of a select minority of state functionaries
21:30
and becomes the task of everyone concerned, only then can freedom be realized.
21:35
Not the abstract sham freedom of the atomized individual,
21:39
but the real freedom that can only be realized through association with others.
21:43
Such a society would have done away with the distinction between civil society and the political state,
21:49
between the individual human and the abstract citizen.
21:54
As usual, no one puts it as beautifully as Marx.
21:57
"Only when the real, individual man re-absorbs in himself the abstract citizen,
22:02
and as an individual human being has become a species-being in everyday life,
22:07
in his particular work, and in his particular situation,
22:10
only when man has recognized and organized his "own powers" as social powers,
22:14
and, consequently, no longer separates social power from himself in the shape of political power,
22:20
only then will human emancipation have been accomplished."
22:24
Such a society may be as hard for us to imagine as it would have been for a serf to imagine ours.
22:30
But it is only when we reject the political dogmas of our times that we can begin to envision emancipation.
22:38
And now, let me thank my private individuals of civil society
22:42
collected here only in pursuit of their own self-interest.
24:05
As well as all of these, private, egoistic individuals.
24:10
I'd also like to thank the fellow YouTubers who read out quotes for this video.
24:14
They are great and you can find their info below.
24:17
This has probably been my hottest take yet, because we're going full radical here on YouTube.
24:23
I hope you enjoyed it, and remember:
24:26
Abolish everything. Thank you.
Comments
Post a Comment